top of page

Suite for Five

1956

  • Choreography: Merce Cunningham

  • Music: John Cage

  • Context: One of the earliest and purest expressions of Cunningham’s and Cage’s philosophy of chance operations, where movement, sound, and time are structured independently. There is no narrative, emotional arc, or hierarchical intention—only coexistence.


Thinking Through Michel Foucault (1926-1984)’s Philosophy on the Art Essence

In Suite for Five, Michel Foucault would witness not merely the unraveling of narrative in dance, but the systematic dismantling of choreographic authorship itself. The work does not represent, does not signify, and refuses to confess. Instead, it performs a radical redistribution of movement, where the dancer is no longer the subject of intention but a locus of indeterminate possibility.


Foucault, especially in his later works on eventality and subjectivation, would read Cunningham’s methodology as a decisive break from the classical and modern traditions of ballet. There is no “Clytemnestra,” no faun, no sailor, no bride. There is only motion without origin, gesture without referent, bodies in space without psychological inscription.


Cunningham, inspired by Cage’s chance operations and Zen aesthetics, refuses the role of the choreographer as sovereign author. Instead, he organizes movement through procedures, algorithms, and rolls of the dice. Foucault would call this a refusal of the author-function—that modern fiction that presumes intention as the source of meaning. Here, intention is displaced by systematic indeterminacy.


This gesture is not a liberation of the dancer—it is a reorganization of power. The dancer is no longer a subject who “expresses,” but rather a subject produced by the intersection of impersonal systems: chance-generated structures, time grids, spatial scores. Foucault would trace this as part of the genealogy of subject-decentering in modernity.


Suite for Five also shatters the unity of time and rhythm. The music, composed independently by John Cage, bears no causal relation to the movement. It coexists, it interferes, but it does not guide. The result is not harmony, but disjunction—a field of asynchronous articulation. Foucault, who analyzed modernity as a space of heterotopias and non-coinciding temporalities, would recognize this as a choreography of the discontinuous.


The spatiality of the piece is equally deconstructed. There is no center stage, no narrative geography. Dancers occupy space through aleatory dispersal. This is not a mise-en-scène—it is a field, an ecology of position, where power does not flow vertically from the choreographer or the “character,” but emerges from relations without hierarchy.


Foucault might compare this with his concept of “evental distribution”—the idea that truth, power, and meaning do not descend from a transcendental source, but are produced through contingent relations, distributions, and spatialities. Suite for Five is not a ballet of being—it is a ballet of appearing, passing, non-totalizable occurrence.


And yet, this refusal to signify is not apolitical. It is an ethics. The dancer here is not governed by emotional logic, narrative arc, or mimetic duty. Instead, the dancer becomes a body-in-relation, subject not to expressive demands, but to the ethics of presence, coexistence, and impermanence. The dancer is not “performing” but tracing a pattern whose source is outside personal will.


Thus, Suite for Five becomes a radical Foucauldian gesture—not a liberation from discipline, but a transformation of the disciplinary regime itself. It marks the passage from representation to multiplicity, from subject to event, from choreography to cartography.


It is not a ballet of intention.


It is a spatial-temporal field of differential emergence.


© 2021-2025 AmKing Association for Holistic Competence Development.

bottom of page